'How
much poorer do we need to be?' asked Ravi, a harassed
and emaciated young autorickshaw driver I recently
met in Bangalore. He was shocked to find out he did
not qualify as 'BPL' (Below Poverty Line), and therefore
won't get what he had hoped for at the ration shop.
As he put it, he and his wife work 'all the time'
and yet with two ailing parents, they were barely
surviving. I suspect our barely surviving millions
live with the same anguish I saw in Ravi's eyes: am
I poor enough to qualify? Will I get a BPL card? Worse
still, our Ravis (or their overworked wives and ailing
parents) have absolutely no voice in determining those
'qualifications' they are required to meet. Being
human is not enough; being citizen is not enough;
being poor and hungry are not enough either. They
have to be exactly as poor and hungry as the government
requires them to be.
This, in essence, is the human face of 'targeting'.
Under targeting, the state establishes criteria to
determine which groups 'truly deserve' whatever benefits
it chooses to offer. Universal regimes, on the other
hand, give benefits to the entire population as a
matter of right. Remember how the IMF championed targeting
during the glorious days of structural adjustment?
It went from country to country forcing states to
dismantle universal social policy regimes and wreaked
havoc on the poor.
It is disconcerting, to say the least, that targeting
seems to be the officially favoured approach with
respect to the Right to Food. With the pervasive nature
of hunger and malnutrition in India today, one might
wonder how a universal right to food can even be in
question. Should every Indian not have a right to
be free from hunger and food insecurity? Should anything
less suffice? I suppose when a government needs court
orders to get rotting grains to its starving citizens,
and a veteran minister 'mistakes' a supreme court
order for a casual suggestion, nothing can be taken
for granted. And now comes the PM's rebuke
to the SC for its alleged intervention in policy-making.
But what about the gross failures of policy-making
that made the court's intervention necessary in the
first place? A targeted approach to food security,
based on a myopic premise of 'resource efficiency'
will be yet another addition to that long line of
policy failures.
What's wrong with targeting?
The argument for targeting is potentially very seductive.
Here is how it goes. If it could, the government would
feed every hungry person. But it can't. It has only
a limited amount of resources, which it cannot 'fritter
away'. Neither does it have enough grain (barring
what is in the warehouses) nor does it have enough
money (barring the revenues it 'foregoes' from the
corporate sector). More importantly, the rich would
abuse the government's goodwill and grab even these
scarce resources. It must choose therefore to feed
only those who are the 'most deserving'. And how does
it do that? Choosing between the rich and poor would
be relatively easy. But in India's vast and growing
landscape of hunger, targeting means choosing between
the destitute, the poor, and the barely surviving;
or if you like, the starving, the chronically hungry,
the malnourished, the anaemic and the food insecure.
While planners and technocrats see important differences
between these categories of people, the truth is that
all of them need food support. None of them earn an
income that can buy a basic, nutrition-adequate food
basket. The real question before us is why this is
the case: why is it that so many people get so little
value for their work that they must go hungry?
Naturally, where the need for support is so pervasive,
targeting constitutes a rather difficult exercise:
an exercise that involves some serious questions of
justice and democracy.
For one, can a right based on 'targeting' be considered
a 'right' at all? It certainly cannot qualify as an
inalienable right as human rights should be, and would
contradict the International
Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.
By vesting in the state the authority to determine
who is entitled to that right, it reduces the 'right'
to a matter of discretion, or at best a a highly tenuous
and negotiable moral obligation. Is it really so different
from you and I trying to help someone in need when
we feel have some money to spare? Legislation based
on such an unclear distinction between rights and
discretion can be rather dangerous, particularly where
so many lives hang in balance.
Second, targeting involves very serious questions
of justice. How can the state justly choose the 'most
deserving'? How does it determine what is a just distribution
of food? As Amartya Sen has warned, consensus on such
questions of justice is difficult to reach and require
reasoned public discussion. 'Reasoned' discussion
however, is rendered difficult, if not impossible,
when unequal power relations exist. Some have the
power to unfairly influence public discourse while
others are marginalized. Most importantly: can the
question be settled justly if the poor and the hungry
are systematically excluded from these discourses?
As of now, the vital norms that determine the lives
of the poor are almost entirely set by others. This
itself is a kind of injustice, of having to live by
norms we have not participated in establishing - but
others have established for us. It violates a basic
principle of self-determination. It reflects, as well,
a structural deficit of democracy, particularly unacceptable
from elites who regularly milk the democracy cow for
electoral gains or for glory at the global stage.
A targeted approach to food (or basic needs) is both
unjust and undemocratic in this sense of denying self-determination.
A universal approach avoids the injustice of violating
self-determination. However, a universal approach
may err in that it treats unequals as equals, by giving
the hungry and the non-hungry the same right. But
so does electoral democracy in deeply unequal societies.
Are we ready to let the poorest have guaranteed rights
to political representation as well? Given the paucity
of honest politicians, how about guaranteeing two
honest politicians per poor person at three rupees
a piece?
Absurdities aside, surely the way to reduce the conflict
between democracy and inequality is to reduce inequality
rather than dilute democracy. The same goes for a
right as vital as the right to food - the solution
is not to restrict the right but to remove the constraints
that prevent it from being enjoyed equally by all.
A targeted approach takes these constraints as given.
It allows the state to constantly invoke those 'constraints',
negotiate its targets and manoeuvre its obligations
to the hungry. The state still retains the power to
decide who it wants to feed and when. The citizens'
right to food becomes a residual of state power.
But most critically: targeting removes from public
scrutiny - and the purview of legislation - the fundamental
reasons as to why the state's constraints come to
exist in the first place. Why
indeed is there not 'enough' money or 'enough' grain?
Could we have more money, for example, by reducing
write-offs to business? Could we have more grain by
reversing policies which force farmers out of farming?
It is precisely in this potential to raise these questions
that the greatest strength of universalism lies. By
giving every citizen a right to food, it creates and
obligation for the state to reorder its priorities,
rather than constantly pleading resource constraints.
It reduces the state's wiggle room to play with hunger.
In sum, it gives the public greater ammunition to
scrutinize how governments define their constraints
and priorities.
Universalism and beyond
A major caveat, however. If our goal is to really
get to the root causes of hunger, then even a universal
right to food will not do: we must insist on a broad
understanding of that right as well. In the current
discussions, 'Right to Food' means the right to consume
a certain amount of food. No more. But the right to
food can go much further than that. As the global
peasant movements demand, the Right to Food must also
include the right to determine how food is produced.
These movements point to a deeper, structural injustice:
the majority of the world's hungry are those who produce
food - but are powerless to determine how food is
produced or consumed. Right now, the power to determine
food production resides with large agribusiness or
with governments. Both are focused on growing 'more'
food: one for profit and the other for political power,
and with terrible consequences.
This is why rich governments are engaging in land
grab of massive proportions. According to a recent
report, some 125 million acres (roughly equal to Sweden)
has been grabbed by rich countries for outsourcing
agricultural production:
''Visit a supermarket in Abu Dhabi and you'll be
greeted by row after row of picture-perfect produce
.. It's likely those rows of shiny vegetables and
fruit came from an improbable source: Ethiopia,
a country practically synonymous with famine. Yes,
Africa, where one in three people is malnourished,
is now growing tomatoes and butter lettuce for export...
Ethiopia's biggest greenhouse farming operation
is kept hidden from curious, or hungry, eyes...''
(See 'Famine-ridden
Ethiopia: What's the new global source for fresh,
shiny produce?')
Some eighty Indian companies, allegedly with support
from the Indian government, are active in this area
as well. In 2009, a
Bangalore-based company with large agricultural projects
in Ethiopia claimed to hold ''one of the largest agriculture
land banks in the world''. As Kenya's Daily Nation
reported in June 2009:
''India leads the "land grabbing" race
and so far Indian agricultural investment has been
more than $2.5 billion. India's total investment
in Ethiopia was $300 million three years ago and
has now grown to $ 4.3 billion. It is double the
amount of Western aid offered to Ethiopia'' (See
'Amid hunger, foreign
companies in race to 'grab' Ethiopia's arable land')
Equally remarkable developments are occurring in
the area of genetic engineering, the other much-loved
'solution' to hunger. For example, the Bill and Melinda
Gates Foundation, Monsanto and USAID have teamed up
to take genetic engineering to new heights. The Foundation
has invested $23.1 million in 500,000 shares of Monsanto
stock. But there is more:
''They also need the power of U.S. government funding.
That is where the U.S. Agency for International
Development and the Casey-Lugar come in. USAID is
now headed up by former Gates employee Rajiv Shah.
The Casey-Lugar Global Food Security act ties foreign
aid to GMOs. When the Gates Foundation places a
bet, they like to hold all the cards.'' See 'Monsanto
in Gates' Clothing? The Emperor's New GMOs')
In this perverse race to grow more food, a justiciable
Right to Food, interpreted narrowly, can become a
dangerous double-edged sword. It may well lend legitimacy
to these anti-people pro-profit growth strategies,
which governments will support in the name of fulfilling
the right to food.
Therefore, along with laws that govern food distribution,
we also need laws that govern food production. We
need laws that prevent profiteering from food and
land and from vesting all food-related decisions with
corporations. Right to Food must also mean that food
producing communities have the right to determine
how food is to be produced. This is what global social
movements are calling food sovereignty, and this is
what people in some of the world's poorest countries
are struggling for. Haitians,
for instance, began to mobilize for food sovereignty
even before they had recovered their loved ones from
the January earthquake. Bolivia, Ecuador, Mali, Senegal
and Venezuela have put food sovereignty in their constitutions.
In India, Kerala's Food Security Action Scheme appears
to go beyond the narrow notion of food security towards
a more comprehensive strategy. The 2008
legislation which aims to prevent paddy-producing
land and wetland from being diverted to other uses,
particularly construction, is an important piece in
this strategy. The Action Scheme also calls explicitly
for rejuvenating fallow land so as to increase agricultural
production. In a fascinating experiment which encourages
women to take up agriculture, the state's anti-poverty
mission, Kudumbashree, has brought some 65,000 acres
of land under cultivation. The cultivators are groups
of women who jointly lease land, cultivate it, decide
how much of their produce they wish to consume and
sell the surplus to local markets. As I travelled
through Kerala to meet Kudumbashree farmers, I was
struck by the changes it has already brought about
in women's lives. Most are/were agricultural labourers
but now see a possibility of becoming independent
producers. For them, the act of farming seemed to
deliver a much stronger, more palpable food security
that came from having control over their production
and their produce. Their biggest problem is indeed
the oldest one: of not owning land. As this experiment
clearly indicates, the right to food cannot be realized
without opening up these classic (and unsettled) questions
of land ownership and agrarian relations.
While many would agree that these questions have serious
implications for food security, they will immediately
warn against 'trying to load too much on to a single
act' (the proposed Food Security Act that is). The
question is not 'how much' but 'what'. Laws/rights
are manifestations of social relations. They can either
simply legitimise unequal social relations or open
up possibilities for changing them.
Universalizing the right to food opens up possible
- albeit not unequivocal - paths to challenge the
unequal social relations which govern the food economy.
A targeted approach on the other hand provides a tool
to manage and legitimize those inequities. And it
gives states and policy-makers the moral impunity
to do so, in the name of serving only the 'truly deserving'.
September
20, 2010. |